# Exploring the Concept: Is the Universe Just a Thought of God?
Written on
Chapter 1: The Nature of Consciousness
What if the essence of consciousness is that it is the sole reality, with everything else, including our physical forms, existing merely as thoughts within this consciousness? This view suggests that the external world was inherently real even before humanity emerged, all contained within the vastness of God's mind. Consequently, all beings, including ourselves, could be seen as manifestations of divine imagination.
This paragraph will result in an indented block of text, typically used for quoting other text.
Section 1.1: Metaphysical Idealism
This perspective aligns with George Berkeley’s well-known metaphysical idealism, which Prudence Louise champions as a valid spiritual worldview. Berkeley recognized an opportunity for theism within empiricism, where knowledge is derived from sensory experience. We can theorize about the existence of matter, but our direct knowledge is limited to our conscious perceptions. Thus, why not entertain a simpler, competing hypothesis: mystical monotheism? In this framework, God is the ultimate reality rather than matter itself, with divine intervention governing everything else.
Louise emphasizes that:
> The entire cosmos is fundamentally rooted in consciousness. There exists only consciousness, and nothing more. Everything you experience, everything you comprehend, is consciousness.
Instead of envisioning the world as residing within your mind, idealism posits that both you and the world are encompassed within a greater consciousness—the mind of God.
God is described as "the necessary foundation of existence," the "absolute," which stands apart from everything else and is "infinite." Louise argues that the benefits of this metaphysical viewpoint are evident. Idealism circumvents the challenges posed by naturalism while embracing scientific advancements as a valid means of acquiring knowledge.
Under idealism, our experiences of the world are genuine. The world truly is as vibrant as it appears, filled with sound, color, fragrance, and flavor. It is not a mere void devoid of meaning or indifferent to existence; rather, reality is imbued with consciousness.
Furthermore, idealism resolves the complex dilemma of how consciousness arises within a material framework. "Consciousness does not emerge from the brain; thus, the end of the body does not signify the end of your existence. Reality is not an insentient mechanism. The world is not devoid of purpose, and your life carries significance."
The naturalist perspective asserts that consciousness emerges from the brain, as if that explanation holds any weight, while the idea of genies emerging from lamps is merely fanciful storytelling. However, both assertions lack any real detail about the mechanisms involved in this supposed emergence.
Instead of relying on a miraculous emergence of the subjective from the objective, we should consider that matter is a product of consciousness. Matter is a state of consciousness—an idea. Observing matter allows one to witness what a specific state of consciousness appears like from an external viewpoint. For the idealist, matter is a concept that facilitates comprehension of the conscious experience.
Matter is not a substance that exists independently of minds; it is merely a product of consciousness.
Section 1.2: The Resistance to Idealism
Why, then, do most individuals cling to the belief that matter is real and exists independently of minds? Louise argues that "humans are attached to their worldviews and do not easily relinquish them." Furthermore, she posits that many fail to grasp that the hard problem of consciousness is "impossible" to solve for naturalists due to its logical nature, rather than merely a lack of empirical evidence.
Chapter 2: The Challenges of Metaphysical Idealism
Despite its allure, metaphysical idealism faces significant hurdles. The Scientific Revolution has rendered many metaphysical concepts, including idealism, nearly obsolete. In our daily lives—especially in business, science, and engineering—we tend to adopt a naturalistic worldview as it offers coherent models that align with observable reality.
Scientific models lean on the existence of matter rather than the notion of an infinite mind filled with mental contents because the latter leads to contradictions and lacks the predictive power of naturalism. Just because metaphysical idealism may provide comfort does not validate its truth.
Consider Louise’s claim that "When you observe matter, you’re seeing what a particular state of consciousness looks like from the outside." The term "outside" implies a spatial relationship that loses meaning if only immaterial minds exist. If minds do not exist in space, how can one be outside of another?
Quantification is inherently materialistic, as counting involves comparing spatial extents. If we can count minds—because there are multiple minds, each with distinct perspectives—we presuppose differing spatial coordinates, contradicting the tenets of metaphysical idealism.
Conversely, if there is only one mind—God's—then metaphysical idealism devolves into solipsism, which Louise rejects.
Additionally, when Louise claims that God "is the absolute ground of all existence, the foundation and source of all knowledge and joy," she unwittingly invokes materialism. The term "ground of being" suggests a spatial reference; if only conscious minds were real, there would be no distinctions of above or below, nor could one entity be "in" another. Such notions contradict the core principles of metaphysical idealism.
Metaphysical idealism offers no better explanation for consciousness than naturalism. In fact, it often explains nothing at all, as the framework is largely untestable and lacks empirical substance.
Louise argues that the notion of consciousness "emerging" from matter is as vacuous as the idea of a genie emerging from a lamp. However, it raises the question: how does the idealist account for God's existence or the creation of other minds? Wouldn't this necessitate invoking a miracle at either stage?
She asserts, “God’s infinite existence overflows, and everything else shares in that existence.” For instance, “His infinite joy spills over, and we partake in that joy. This participation isn’t separate from God; everything exists within God.”
Yet these statements rely on spatial concepts. What does it mean for immaterial minds and their contents to "flow"? How can one immaterial mind exist "within" another? Such language is convoluted, which is why few embrace metaphysical idealism.
Louise proposes that the brain does not generate consciousness; rather, it constrains consciousness within certain parameters, limiting our awareness of reality. However, this brain-as-filter concept is just as susceptible to the hard problem as the idea of the brain as a substrate for emergence. Claiming that consciousness filters through the brain is akin to saying that the bottle contains the genie. There is no real explanatory advantage, and the mechanism remains as mysterious as before.
The idealist does not elucidate consciousness but rather treats it as a metaphysical primitive that requires no further explanation. The burden of the idealist is to clarify how matter derives from consciousness rather than the opposite. Unfortunately, no such explanation appears forthcoming.
Louise's discourse is riddled with spatial metaphors that inadvertently imply materialism, undermining her metaphysical assertions. Invoking an infinite, absolute being is a deus ex machina that fails to meet scientific standards of rationality. While an infinite being could theoretically resolve various quandaries regarding the nature of reality, it does not provide clarity on how God could manifest such phenomena, thus failing to illuminate rather than obscure the issues at hand.
Consider how religious narratives often incorporate elements of reality, making them seem to contribute to our understanding of the universe. For instance, biblical accounts describe God hovering over primordial waters and speaking forms into existence.
This intuitive connection to language gives the illusion of comprehension, despite the fact that the biblical creation process is fundamentally miraculous. Language has been essential in forming civilizations; without it, coordinating collective efforts would have been impossible. The ancient Jews presumed that language was equally vital to God's creative process.
However, this analogy collapses upon examination; language serves as a communication tool for multiple minds. If God was solitary when creating the universe, why would He need language? To whom would He have been communicating in a monotheistic framework? The human-centered metaphor is incompatible with the singular divine essence, just as the spatial metaphors of metaphysical idealism lack coherence within an immaterialist context.
Religious creation myths present various pseudo-mechanisms, be it gods birthing nature or crafting it from a dragon's remains. These tales resonate with human intuition, yet the premise that such intuitions help us understand the vast cosmos is flawed.
Chapter 3: The Limitations of Idealism
The most significant shortcoming of metaphysical idealism is its inability to differentiate itself from naturalism through the provision of testable predictions or enhancements to materialistic models that explain scientific observations.
Assuming only minds exist, including God's, how would we account for the formation of our solar system from an idealistic standpoint? Humans were absent at that time, implying that God must have been involved. This notion implies a temporal sequence that is nonsensical unless materialism is accepted, contradicting the logic of metaphysical idealism.
What does it mean for one mind to precede another in time? Time itself must be a concept within God's mind, but if this concept logically leads to materialism (as in Einsteinian physics), enabling the idealist to explain phenomena like solar system formation, then metaphysical idealism undermines itself.
Materialism, too, would be a divine concept that proves useful in elucidating various natural occurrences. The idealist's religious background merely enriches the efficacy of naturalism with the belief that all scientific principles and models function because they exist within God's consciousness.
To justify why one should embrace this immaterialist metaphysics, a rationale must exist to prefer it over naturalism. Spiritual idealism fails to offer ontological simplicity, as it lacks explanatory power without presupposing spatial and temporal frameworks.
Louise contends that idealism alone can clarify consciousness; however, evidence suggests no advantage in this regard. Moreover, idealism does not clarify how conscious minds relate to God in a manner that would facilitate empirical testing, preventing a fair comparison between the two worldviews.
For example, if metaphysical idealism holds true and a halo forms around the head of anyone who realizes that matter is illusory, it might be because idealists communicate more directly with God's mind by grasping the insubstantiality of matter and evading distractions from their relationship with God, the "ground" of all being.
In this scenario, we could explore a psychological mechanism ripe for testing. Do halos exclusively manifest around those who adhere to metaphysical idealism? Does the halo's shape or color shift based on the quality of their relationship with God? Could individuals closely aligned with their creator perform miraculous acts akin to Neo in "The Matrix"? If matter is merely an illusion and "there is no spoon," perhaps we would expect spiritualists to perform wonders that would awaken us from the misconception that matter is real, a distraction from God's paramount importance.
However, if parapsychology were disproven scientifically, it would undermine the implications of metaphysical idealism. While spiritualists may feel empowered, they possess no objective, miraculous advantages over naturalists in navigating life. Consequently, metaphysical idealism appears insubstantial and unfalsifiable as a worldview, making it rationally dismissible under the epistemic standards established by philosophers to account for the remarkable success of scientific methodologies.
I compile my writings on Medium into both paperback and eBook formats, available on Amazon for those interested in having them accessible and supporting my work. Recent titles include "Our Oddity in Deep Time," "Aristocrats in the Wild," and "Questing for Epiphanies in a Haunted House," each containing over 500 pages filled with my essays on philosophy, religion, and politics.
The first video titled "Is God the Best Explanation for the Beginning of the Universe?" explores whether God's existence offers a more satisfactory explanation for the universe's origins than naturalistic views.
The second video titled "Does the Fine Tuning of the Universe Demonstrate the Existence of God?" investigates whether the precise conditions necessary for life suggest the presence of a divine creator.